The Pleasures of Anger: Insights from Aristotle and Kant on Getting Mad, Staying Mad, and Doing This With Others
I am in the early stages of undertaking a monograph on the pleasures of anger. This project begins from the question, 'Why anger?', or more precisely, 'Why do people get angry when they do rather than some other response?'. A person can perceive and fight against injustice without feeling angry, so what does anger accomplish? I will show a crucial part of any satisfactory answer is that anger is in some way pleasant. This idea that anger is tied to pleasure may appear paradoxical from the viewpoint of commonsense psychology, which characterizes experiences of anger, along with other negative affects, as painful. Yet anger can have its pleasures without anger being experienced by the subject as pleasurable overall. Different sorts of pleasures can be identified within the experience of getting angry, but the pleasure of anger in the most fundamental sense is found in how being angry enables the angry person to claim, assert, and begin to restore their lost standing from the perceived injustice.
While this analysis proceeds from the individual's experience of anger, the focus of the book is on how anger can be something that a group of people do together. Pleasure is necessary for explaining how the character of the anger itself is changed when anger is done by an individual or done as a group. At the individual level, pleasure is key for explaining not just why anger is preferable to other sorts of feelings in response to the intentional object of the anger, but also why someone may want to stay with their anger, or even return to some anger after setting it aside. This possibility — that feeling angry can be not only an immediate emotional response to a perceived injustice, but a kind of activity that can be voluntarily taken up and also put aside — can be glimpsed within some individual experiences of anger, but anger as an activity is fundamentally something people do together, with individuals entering into and tabling some socially-shared anger at their convenience. Certain features are distinctive of the activity of anger as done by more than one person. The object of the group anger will be more diffuse, as this is necessary for different persons to partake in feeling angry towards it. Group anger will be less easy to resolve, since there is not usually a clear, unitary account of the wrong suffered and the appropriate remedy for this wrong. In general, group anger will be less practical in its orientation than individual anger: in some vital way, the point or goal of individual anger is to secure redress for the wrong suffered, including revenge upon the wrongdoer, whereas the point or goal of group anger is primarily the feeling of anger itself. In being done primarily for the feeling itself and so for its own sake, group anger is even more self-sustaining than individual anger. Moreover, in being done simply for the experience of doing/feeling it, and so becoming something like an end-in-itself, group anger becomes in its formal structure more like pleasure.